. . . . . . "Receptivity implies that we can have knowledge only of what can affect us. Irreducibility implies, in Kant's view, that intrinsic properties cannot affect us. Humility follows from these. This interpretation finds support in a range of critical and pre-critical writings, but there is a special focus on an early anti-Leibnizian argument for irreducibility that has considerable philosophical merit. One advantage of this interpretation is that the following famous contradiction is dissolved: things in themselves exist, and are the causes of phenomena, and we have no knowledge of them as they are in themselves. Moreover Kant's scientific realism, surprising on an idealist interpretation, makes sense."@en . "Langton offers an interpretation and defence of Kant's doctrine of things in themselves. She aims to vindicate Kant's scientific realism, and show his primary/secondary quality distinction to be superior." . . . . "Kantian humility our ignorance of things in themselves"@en . "Kantian humility our ignorance of things in themselves" . . "Livres électroniques" . . "Kantian Humility Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves" . . . . . . . . . "Academic dissertations"@en . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . "Kantian Humility : our ignorance of things in themselves" . . . "Kantian humility : our ignorance of things in themselves" . "Kantian humility : our ignorance of things in themselves"@en . . . . . . "Kantian humility"@en . "Kantian humility" . . . . "It does not conflict with Kant's (apparently Berkeleyan) claim that he makes all the qualities secondary--he means that he makes them powers, or in Locke's terms, tertiary qualities. Kant's \"primary\"/secondary quality distinction is superior to widely accepted alternatives, and his application of the irreducibility argument to the primary qualities challenges some current orthodoxies. Kant's commitment to the unobservables of science is permitted by his understanding of receptivity: we can have knowledge of anything that can affect us. Kant's scientific realism, and his humility, thus have a common source."@en . . "The distinction at the heart of Kant's philosophy is a metaphysical distinction: things in themselves are substances, bearers of intrinsic properties; phenomena are relational properties of substances. Kant says that things as we know them are composed \"entirely of relations\", by which he means forces. Kant's claim that we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic properties of substances. Kant has an empiricist starting-point. Human beings are receptive creatures. We must be affected by the things of which we come to have knowledge. Kant believes that humility follows from this fact of receptivity. Humility does follow from receptivity, once a further premise is supplied. Kant believes that relational properties, causal powers in particular, are not reducible to intrinsic properties, and that intrinsic properties are therefore causally inert."@en . "Llibres electrònics" . "Rae Langton offers a new interpretation and defence of Kant's doctrine of things in themselves. Kant distinguishes things in themselves from phenomena, and in so doing he makes a metaphysical distinction between intrinsic and relational properties of substances. Langton argues that his claim that we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but epistemic humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic properties of substances. This interpretation vindicates Kant's scientific realism, and shows his primary/secondary quality distinction to be superior even to modern-day competitors. And it answers the famous charge that Kant's tale of things in themselves is one that makes itself untellable. - ;Rae Langton offers a new interpretation and defence of Kant's doctrine of things in themselves. Kant distinguishes things in themselves from phenomena, and in so doing he makes a metaphysical distinction between intrinsic and relational properties of substances. Kant says that phenomena--things as we know them--consist 'entirely of relations', by which he means forces. His claim that we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but epistemic humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic properties of substances. This humility has its roots in some plausible philosophical beliefs: an empiricist belief in the receptivity of human knowledge and a metaphysical belief in the irreducibility of relational properties. Langton's interpretation vindicates Kant's scientific realism, and shows his primary/secondary quality distinction to be superior even to modern-day competitors. And it answers the famous charge that Kant's tale of things in themselves is one that makes itself untellable." . . . . . . . . . "Electronic books" . "Electronic books"@en . . "Langton offers an interpretation and defence of Kant's doctrine of things in themselves. He aims to vindicate Kant's scientific realism, and show his primary/secondary quality distinction to be superior." . . . . "Metaphysik." . . "chose en soi (philosophie) Kant, Immanuel." . . "Cosa en si." . . "Humility Philosophy." . . "Chose en soi." . . "Humilitat." . . "Erkenntnistheorie." . . "Metafysica." . . "PHILOSOPHY Metaphysics." . . "Objet (philosophie)" . . "Objet (philosophie)." . "Phénomène (philosophie)" . . "Nederigheid." . . "Oxford University Press." . . "Kennistheorie." . . "Ding an sich." . . "Ding an sich" . "Philosophy." . . "Noumenon." . . "Knowledge, Theory of." . . "Langton, Rae" . . "Phénoménisme." . .